Copyright©James
Jope
Aristotle has always
been recognized as a major philosopher, but his biology has received
less attention from philosophers than the subjects which are still
regarded as philosophy today, such as metaphysics. Modern science, on
the other hand, developed largely in opposition to Aristoteleans, and
most scientists have little interest in the Stagyrite’s superceded
achievement. Those who do (e.g.,Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker) sometimes find his thought surprisingly
compatible with their own.
The
two books on Aristotle’s
biological work reviewed here
open intriguing new
perspectives. One exhibits
recent work in the budding discipline of the philosophy of biology,
and the other
is a balanced appreciation of Aristotle as a scientist by an informed
biologist.
While
the philosophers derive from Aristotle interesting solutions to modern
issues in the philosophy of biology, the biologist shows a more
empathetic understanding of the Stagirite’s life and method.
Heinemann, Gottfried and Rainer Timme (edd.).
Aristoteles und die heutige Biologie: vergleichende Studien. Lebenswissenschaften im Dialog, 17. Freiburg; München: Verlag Karl Alber, 2017. 352 p. € 39.00 (pb). ISBN 9783495486924.
Leroi, Armand Marie.
The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. London: Bloomsbury, hb 2014; pb 2015, 502 p., £9.99, ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4
Aristoteles und die heutige Biologie is a collection of papers
originally presented at a conference at Kassel University in 2009. The
contents are shown at the end of this review.
Georg Toepfer opens his essay with these words: “Die Teleologie des
Organischen bei Aristoteles soll in diesem Beitrag nicht primaer aus der
Perspektive der Aristoteles-Forschung untersucht werden, sondern aus
der Perspektive der Philosophie der Biologie und deren Diskussionsstand
der letzten Jahrzehnte.” The same could be said of most of the papers in
Heinemann and Timme. The book could have been titled “Aristotle and
Biophilosophy”; there is much on issues like teleology, ontogeny and
Aristotle’s hylomorphic theory of body and soul as ontologically
inseparable aspects of a single entity (matter and form, respectively),
but only a secondary interest in the Stagirite’s extensive empirical
observations and analyses. Contributors occasionally disagree, launching
philosophical discussions from their Aristotelian point of departure.
The essays are arranged in five parts and summarized on p. 19-22.
Biophilosophy has become well established in recent decades, and a focus
on Aristotle is welcome.
Readers who may have expected a study of Aristotle more specifically
qua biologist will like Armand Marie Leroi’s
The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science.
Leroi is a professor of evolutionary developmental biology who, taking
as a role model D’Arcy Thompson, another biology professor who could not
restrain his interest in classical studies, undertook to master
adequate classical scholarship to freshly interpret Aristotle showing
how a scientist can offer new insights concerning the ancient
philosopher.
Turning first to Heinemann and Timme, Gottfried Heinemann’s own
contribution is a thorough study of problematic Aristotelian texts cited
in an ongoing dispute with David Sedley and others. Sedley has
postulated that ‘nature’ (
physis) must mean a global figure like
the modern ‘Nature’ in passages where, for example, Aristotle says that
plants and animals are made by ‘Nature’ for man’s benefit. Heinemann
insists that Aristotle’s
physis is always only the nature or
‘form’ of a particular species. This controversy cannot be resolved
here. If we accept the orthodox assumption that Aristotle gradually
distanced himself from Plato, Heinemann’s view fits more smoothly with
Aristotle’s mature philosophy, in which there is neither creation nor a
providential agent. A global Nature is rather reminiscent of Plato’s
creating demiurge. Yet I believe that Sedley’s interpretation of some
texts is more straightforward, while Heinemann’s seems forced.
It is regrettable that Heinemann chose to quote these texts only in
translation. Readers following a controversy over verbal usage need to
see the Greek. Jochen Althoff, to his credit, is the only contributor
who reproduces extensive quotations in Greek. When his opponent Georg
Toepfer discusses a familiar “
zentrale Textstelle” from Aristotle on p. 294, he assesses conflicting translations without even providing a reference to the Greek text.
Althoff and Toepfer dispute to what extent Aristotle can be credited as
the source of the concept of an ‘organism’ even though he did not use
the word. They agree that some features of the concept, such as
describing the living entity and its organs in terms of functional
teleology (the eye is to see, etc.), are Aristotelian. But Toepfer
disputes Althoff’s ascription of the origin of the concept to Aristotle.
A critical feature of the modern concept of an organism is the
interdependency of its organs. Althoff suggests that the processing of
food by heat into blood and then sperm or menstrual blood as it passes
through the body—i.e., the basic animal functions of nutrition and
reproduction according to Aristotle—is an interaction of the organs
comparable to metabolism. Toepfer argues that Aristotle’s use of the
soul as the organizing principle in an animal, instead of just the
interaction of the organs themselves, kept him from realizing the
importance of their interaction, which Toepfer believes was first
acknowledged with the concept of ‘sympathy’ in Galen and the Stoics.
But arguably, the Stoics too employed an organizing principle, viz., the
‘fire’ which energizes organisms and the universe.
The key to such disputes is, of course, how generous one wishes to be
towards Aristotle, how closely his theories must approximate their
modern comparanda.
Niko Strobach shows how reducing two compared theories to exact
propositions on which both would agree formulated in symbolic logic can
reveal unexpected similarities and differences. This method might be
useful in settling disputes. However, for Strobach’s own example
regarding the constancy of species he has to dwell disproportionately on
exceptional cases such as mules to obtain significant results. If we
try to reduce, e.g., Althoff’s metabolic comparison to such a statement,
it would be trivial: “Living things ingest and assimilate materials
from outside.” Thus, crude comparisons which may nevertheless have
heuristic or historical value could be rejected.
The essays by Kirsten Schmidt, Kristian Koechy, and Martin Norwig all
discuss important issues of modern biology and indicate solutions
proposed by other philosophers which they believe to be compatible with
Aristotle.
Schmidt and Koechy review historical theories of ontogeny (embryological
development) after Aristotle, leading up to the deciphering of the
genetic code, and then show that more recent biological evidence
following that discovery does not support the common view that genes
exclusively dictate the complete development of an organism. Popularly
promoted by Richard Dawkins (
The Selfish Gene 1978), this meme is
typified in the current cliché that any interest or achievement of an
individual “is in her DNA”. This oversimplified belief still largely
dominates popular opinion, so that these papers are timely and
constructive. However, the respective alternatives proposed by the
authors are diametrically opposed.
According to the meme, the genome comprises a program which solely
determines and controls the development of an organism, a role
comparable to that of Aristotle’s ‘form’ or ‘soul’. However, further
research has revealed other, ‘epigenetic’ causal factors. For example,
activation of the genes to develop particular body parts can be
determined by their position in a foetus through chemical gradients.
Such positional mechanisms were explored in depth by Gerald M. Edelman
(1988), who coined for them the term ‘topobiology’. For a proper
understanding of the interaction between genes and other embryological
factors, Schmidt advocates Susan Oyama’s ‘Developmental Systems Theory’ (
The Ontogeny of Information
1985), which follows the ontogenetic process without postulating any
one guiding agent, be it ‘form’ or genome. For Schmidt, ontogenetic
development is contingent on environmental influences to such an extent
that it has no regular final outcome. That allows for the long-term
evolutionary variation of species but does not explain their short-term
constancy. As for Aristotle, Schmidt does not adequately discriminate
between his hylomorphic soul, which is inseparable from the body, and
the Platonic-Christian version, a vitalist “
Entitaet… die zum Entwicklungsprozess in einer Beziehung von Schoepfer und Schoepfung steht” (p. 79, my emphasis).
According to Koechy, Aristotle’s view tracing the ‘form’ of the species to the father (“
anthropos anthropon genna”)
prevailed until twentieth-century biologists located it either in the
genes (molecular biology) or in populations (evolutionary biology).
However, some (Ernst Mayr and Stephen J. Gould are best known) have
argued that the focus should return to individuals, as they both control
epigenetic factors and supply the mutations on which natural selection
works. Koechy refers to Denis Walsh (
Evolutionary Essentialism
2006) to restore an essentialist view more like Aristotle’s by rewording
the principles of natural selection: For example, instead of describing
the environment as selecting mutations, we should say that the
mutations must occur in a sufficient number of individuals to become
established.
Norwig discusses the issue of physicalist reductionism, i.e., the belief
that biological phenomena can be explained by the underlying purely
physical properties, so that biology should eventually no longer be a
separate science from physics. He surveys variants of physicalism from
the extreme version proposed by logical positivists early in the last
century to moderate recent models which allow some scope to study such
concepts as evolution or biodiversity, and finally advocates J. Kim’s
‘supervenience’, a special type of covariance between two sets of
properties, physical and biological, such that the latter are dependent
on the former but without any assumption of causality. Norwig argues
that this concept accommodates such recent advances as the correlation
of mental processes with physical events in the brain in cognitive
science. He compares the supervenient correlation of cephalic and mental
processes with Aristotle’s hylomorphism. This comparison is workable,
but only insofar as the soul is inseparable from the body. However, led
by his own choice of cognitive science as an example, Norwig applies the
theory to mind and thought without any mention of Aristotle’s belief in
an ‘agent intellect’ which is separable from the body—a remnant of
Platonism, perhaps, but if one must discuss cognitive activities, it
should be considered.
What this book offers is a philosophical discussion positioning
Aristotle on issues in the philosophy of biology. The issues are current
and the overall understanding of Aristotle is satisfactory, but the
emphasis is on modern biophilosophical theory. It may be symptomatic in
this regard that while these authors turn to (modern) third-party
theorists to bridge Aristotle with modern thinking, Leroi argues that
Aristotle himself is compatible with modern findings if correctly
interpreted.
As mentioned above, Leroi, who teaches developmental biology at the
university of London, set out to interpret Aristotle from a biologist’s
point of view. From his own experience he can tell when Aristotle
actually did perform a dissection, how he made mistakes, and when he
only read other sources; Aristotle did not dissect a dolphin, but he
definitely did dissect cuttlefish. Leroi also observes, for example,
that Aristotle’s account of animal life cycles satisfies the modern
finding that the reproductive fertility of a species is inversely
proportional to its infant mortality rate and longevity, a relationship
which scholars may fail to appreciate in Aristotle.
As scholarly sources he lists David Balme, Allan Gotthelf, Wolfgang
Kullmann, James Lennox, Goffrey Lloyd, and Pierre Pellegrin, but his
reading extends beyond these in ancient as well as modern sources,
including not only philosophers like Empedocles, but miscellaneous
authors such as Athenaeus.
Whereas contributors to Heinemann and Timme compare historical
background material mainly after Aristotle, Leroi’s historical
comparisons relate Aristotle back to Empedocles, Democritus and the
Hippocratics, as well as forwards to Cuvier, Harvey etc.
His account of Aristotle’s four causes exemplifies the biological
orientation which characterizes the entire book:
“The efficient (or moving) cause is an account of the mechanics and
movement of change. It is now the domain of developmental biology and
neurophysiology… The formal cause is an account of the information
transmitted that any creature received from its parents, and that is
responsible for the features that it shares with other members of its
species—that is, the subject matter of genetics. The final cause is
teleology, the analysis of the parts of animals in terms of their
functions. It is now the part of evolutionary biology that studies
adaptation.” (p. 92). However, Leroi also targets a wider audience. He
personally retraced Aristotle’s expedition to a lagoon at Pyrrha where
they both collected specimens, and he enlivens his account with
descriptions of local flora, fauna and topology, with sometimes
irrelevant illustrations, and with amusing, albeit patronizing reports
of encounters with Greek fishermen.
Some of these efforts to make the book attractive for any educated
reader may deter scholars. I have not reproduced the table of contents,
because it is not a useful guide: It mysteriously lists a chapter on
“The Soul of the Cuttlefish”, which turns out to discuss
de Anima. “Instruments” is about the
Organon. “Foam” is
de generatione Animalium,
and “Figs, Honey and Fish” concerns life cycles. The reason for this is
that it is precisely with regard to these organisms that Leroi analyses
Aristotle’s doctrines. The cuttlefish chapter, for example, gives a
full account of the nutritive soul, in which Leroi too compares its
action to metabolism. However, scholars will find little guidance to
specific topics apart from the index. Documentation is provided in
endnotes and appendices, but when Aristotle’s text is quoted the reader
will not always find an exact reference. Footnotes serve, instead, to
enlighten the classical reader on relevant aspects of science, or the
scientist on additional ancient material.
On page after page, Leroi illustrates zoologically relevant aspects of
Aristotle’s thought in concrete examples from the biological treatises.
He shows how Aristotle used the interaction of functional teleology (the
eye is to see) and ‘conditional necessity’ (if it is to see, it must be
vitreous) to approximate in his static species a modern understanding
of adaptation. Leroi even has a plausible argument to relate Aristotle’s
scientific method to biology:
“For all its limitations, Aristotle’s theory of demonstration is a
genuine scientific method. It is part of ours. Scientists may quarrel
about methodology but… They understand the domain of science… They
understand… the reciprocal role of theory and evidence and the
distinction between hypothesis and fact. They understand that science
begins with induction to give generalizations from observations and then
deduction to give firm causal claims from generalizations… That they
understand all this is because Aristotle told them it was so.” (p.
131-2).
But beyond this, he grapples with overall issues like the unity and
chronology of Aristotle’s thought. He is sometimes less impressive here,
as when he explains the cosmos as an organism or compares ‘natural
slaves’ to modern factory workers, but it does enable this book to serve
as a complete introduction to Aristotle.
Leroi’s major criticisms of Aristotle—and they are undoubtedly
correct--are that his rejection of atomism and his embrace of
‘homoiomerous’ basic materials led to errors throughout his work; and
that methodically looking for the truth in received wisdom made him too
conservative. Regarding spontaneous generation, for example, Leroi
argues that it was contrary to Aristotle’s own theories, and then
proceeds to show how, step by step, Leeuwenhoek and others refuted
it—with a nod to Homer.
Leroi’s exploration of Aristotle and his lagoon is a captivating
interdisciplinary disquisition, and both books offer a wealth of
material for reception studies.